IR Folks from Times Past

IR Folks from Times Past

Saturday, August 17, 2013

Machiavellism and Its Enemies

Friedrich Meinecke’s great study of Machiavellism appeared originally in German in 1924. This extract is from the 1957 translation published by Yale University Press. Here Meinecke gives the kernel of his interpretation of the significance of reason of state, and presents a dramatic contrast between Machiavelli and Grotius:

* * *

[T]he modern Western world has inherited one legacy of extraordinary importance from the Christian and Germanic Middle Ages. It has inherited a sharper and more painful sense of the conflict between raison d'etat on the one hand, and ethics and law on the other; and also the feeling which is constantly being aroused, that ruthless raison d'etat is really sinful, a sin against God and divine standards, a sin against the sanctity and inviolability of the law of the good old times. The ancient world was already familiar with these sins of raison d'etat, and did not omit to criticize them, but without taking them very much to heart. The very secularity of human values in the ancient world made it possible to view raison d'etat with a certain calmness and to consider it the outcome of natural forces which were not to be subdued. Sinfulness in antiquity was still a perfectly naive sinfulness, not yet disquieted and frightened by the gulf between heaven and hell which was to be opened up by Christianity. This dualistic picture of the world, which was held by dogmatic Christianity, has had a deep influence even on the period of a Christianity that is growing undogmatic; and it has given the problem of raison d'etat this deeply felt overtone of tragedy, which it never carried in antiquity.

It was therefore a historical necessity that the man, with whom the history of the idea of raison d'etat in the modern Western world begins and from whom Machiavellism takes its name, had to be a heathen; he had to be a man to whom the fear of hell was unknown, and who on the contrary could set about his life-work of analysing the essence of raison d'etat with all the naivety of the ancient world.

Niccolo Machiavelli was the first to do this. We are concerned here with the thing itself, not with the name for it, which he still did not possess. Machiavelli had not yet compressed his thoughts on raison d'etat into a single slogan. Fond as he was of forceful and meaningful catch-words (coining many himself), he did not always feel the need to express in words the supreme ideas which filled him; if, that is, the thing itself seemed to him self-evident, if it filled him completely. For example, critics have noticed that he fails to express any opinion about the real final purpose of the State, and they have mistakenly deduced from this that he did not reflect on the subject. But, as we shall soon see, his whole life was bound up with a definite supreme purpose of the State. And in the same way his whole political way of thought is nothing else but a continual process of thinking about raison d'etat.

* * *

The most serious discrepancy in his system of thought—a discrepancy which he never succeeded in eliminating and which he never even tried to eliminate—lay between the newly discovered ethical sphere of virtú, and of the State animated by virtú, on the one hand, and the old sphere of religion and morality on the other. This virtú of Machiavelli was originally a natural and dynamic idea, which (not altogether unhappily) contained a certain quality of barbarity (ferocia); he now considered that it ought not to remain a mere unregulated natural force (which would have been in accordance with the spirit of the Renaissance) but that it ought to be raised into a virtú ordinata, into a rationally and purposively directed code of values for rulers and citizens. The virtú ordinata naturally set a high value on religion and morality, on account of the influence they exerted towards maintaining the State. In particular, Machiavelli spoke out very forcibly on the subject of the indispensability of religion (Disc., I, 11 and 12); at any rate, he was strongly in favour of a religion which would make men courageous and proud. He once named “religion, laws, military affairs” together in one breath, as the three fundamental pillars of the State. But, in the process, religion and morality fell from the status of intrinsic values, and became nothing more than means towards the goal of a State animated by virtú. It was this that led him on to make the double-edged recommendation, which resounded so fearsomely down the centuries to come, inciting statesmen to an irreligious and at the same time dishonest scepticism: the advice that even a religion tinged with error and deception ought to be supported, and the wiser one was, the more one would do it (Disc., I, 12). Whoever thought like this was, from a religious point of view, completely adrift. What final certainty and sure foundation was there left in life, if even an unbelieved and false religion could count as valuable, and when moral goodness was seen as being a product of fear and custom? In this godless world of Nature man was left alone with only himself and the powers Nature had given him, to carry on the fight against all the fateful forces wielded by this same Nature. And this was exactly what Machiavelli conceived his own situation to be.

It is striking and forceful to observe how he strove to rise superior to it. On the one side fortuna, on the other virtú—this was how he interpreted it. Many people today (he says in ch. 25 of the Principe), in the face of the various blows of Fate and unsuspected revolutions we have experienced, are now of the opinion that all wisdom is entirely unavailing against the action of Fate, and that we must just let it do what it likes with us. He admits that even he himself has occasionally felt like this, when in a gloomy mood. But he considered it would be lacking in virtu to surrender to the feeling. One must rouse oneself and build canals and dams against the torrent of Fate, and then one will be able to keep it within bounds. . . .

Enemies learn to use each other's weapons. Virtú has the task of forcing back fortuna. Fortuna is malicious, so virtú must also be malicious, when there is no other way open. This expresses quite plainly the real spiritual origin of Machiavellism: the infamous doctrine that, in national behaviour, even unclean methods are justified, when it is a question of winning or of keeping the power which is necessary for the State. It is the picture of Man, stripped of all transcendent good qualities, left alone on the battlefield to face the daemonic forces of Nature, who now feels himself possessed too of a daemonic natural strength and returns blow for blow.

* * *

The one who remained furthest from these problems was Hugo Grotius, the principal founder of modern international law. This was due to the nature of his task. International law and raison d'etat stand in natural opposition to one another. International law wishes to restrict the sway of raison d'etat, and give it as much of a legal character as possible. Raison d'etat, however, chafes under this restriction, and makes use of law, in fact very frequently misuses it, as a means towards its own egotistical ends. By doing so, raison d'etat is continually shatter­ing the foundations which international law has just painfully attempted to lay. In many ways, international law is performing a labour of Sisyphus by struggling with raison d'etat; and this tends to become more so, the less international law troubles itself about the essential nature and requirements of raison d'etat. For then it is in danger, from the outset, of becoming unreal, unpractical and doctrinaire. And however great were the intellectual accomplishments and scientific credit due to Grotius, yet he himself succumbed to this danger on a number of essential points. It was not as if this arose from any lack of knowledge about political reality. When, in Paris in 1625, he finished his great work De jure belli ac pacis, he already possessed a wealth of political experi­ence, and had tasted the sorrows of the political refugee. He knew the world, and knew what statecraft was; but he deliberately kept this knowledge quite apart from his work. 'I have abstained from every­thing', he says in the Introduction, 'that belongs to other provinces, such as the doctrine of what is profitable, since this belongs to the special art of politics. I have only mentioned these other questions quite perfunctorily in different places, in order to distinguish them more clearly from the question of law'. Scientific thought, having not yet become properly adjusted to the organic reciprocal effects of the various provinces of life, could find no other way of keeping them all logically separate from one another, except the superficial method of treating each one in complete isolation. And so Grotius constructed his system of international law, just as if there did not exist any such thing as raison d'etat, or any constraining force tending to push States over the frontiers of morality and law; just as if it were possible altogether to confine the behaviour of States to one another within legal and moral bounds. In the process, he mingled law and morality together promiscuously at every step. But standing behind all this were his own view of life and his own personality, which was altogether noble, gentle and full of human feeling. He built up his ideas about law and the State on the foundation of a belief in humanity, a belief in the sociable and altruistic impulses of men, and a belief especially in the solidarity of the Christian peoples. In him, the old traditions of the Corpus Christianum were already passing over into the modern civil and liberal ideals of life, infused with feeling, such as were now capable of developing amongst the Dutch commercial aristocracy. He, the advocate of arbitration in conflict between nations, is entitled to a much larger place in the history of the pacifist idea than in the history of the idea of raison d'etat. His feeling was decidedly unheroic when he advised conquered nations that it was better for them to accept their fate, than to continue a hopeless struggle for their freedom—since reason valued life more highly than it did freedom! This was also a utilitarian way of thinking; but he looked upon raison d'etat and the policy of interest as a lower form of usefulness, compared with the higher and more permanent advantage afforded by the maintenance of natural law and the international law of nations. And even if (he added) one might not be able to see any profit in acting in accordance with justice, it would still be a matter of wisdom and not stupidity to act in that manner to which we feel drawn by our nature.

Certainly the struggle, waged by his international law and usage of war against barbarism and crude force, was productive of many blessings; and, in spite of the fact that more than one of its requirements has proved excessive, it has also exerted a beneficial influence on the practice of nations. Indeed it is seldom that great ethical ideals arise in life which do not carry with them some admixture of illusion. But he firmly believed in the old illusion, that it would always be possible to distinguish the 'just war' from the wars that were unjust and impermissible; and this illusion was capable of actually increasing the difficulty of the situations, and of increasing rather than lessening the sources of conflict and occasions of war. He declared that it was the duty of neutrals to do nothing which was capable of strengthening the defender of the bad cause, or of hindering the enterprise of the just cause. But what could this mean, except that the neutral should take sides, on the basis of a judgment of moral value, which would always tend to be influenced by his personal interest, by his raison d'etat? Indeed even wars of intervention, undertaken for motives of pure morality and justice, in order to punish a glaring injustice by a ruler against his subjects, or crude infringements of international law and the law of nature, were held by him to be unjustified. That cases could arise, in which the conscience of the whole civilized world might cry out against one who scorned justice and humanity, and interfere with full authority to stop it, is a fact which has to be recognized even today, and indeed particularly today. But every influx of unpolitical motives into the province of pure conflicts of power and interest brings with it the danger that these motives will be misused and debased by the naturally stronger motives of mere profit, of raison d'etat. The latter resembles some mud-coloured stream that swiftly changes all the purer waters flowing into it into its own murky colour. The wars of intervention during the period of the Holy Alliance, and the misuse of moral and legal motives by Germany's opponents during the World War, offer proof of this.

 
* * *

Friedrich Meinecke, Machiavellism: The Doctrine of Raison D’Etat And Its Place in Modern History. Translated from the German by Douglas Scott (New York, Praeger, 1965 [1924, 1957]  28-29, 35-36, 208-210. Meinecke's reflections were published in 1924 and still reflected, despite the disaster of the First World War, basic themes of German nationialism and Machtpolitik.  Daniel Deudney, in Bounding Power, p. 72, has a a poignant summary of Meinecke's position after the "much more complete disaster of the Third Reich and World War II." In The German Catastrophe, published in the 1950s, Meinecke   

becomes completely disillusioned with the political nation and nationalism and offers something of an autopsy of the radicalized national statist line of argument. He acknowledges that the "German power-state idea" finds "in Hitler its worst and most fatal application and extension" and says that "our conception of power must be purified from the filth which came into it during the Third Reich" and that "the purpose of power must be reflected upon and wisely limited.'' Rejecting the "fighting folk character" culminating in Hitlerism, he urges a return to the cultural nationalism of "the peaceful volk character" with its "genuine Romanticism." He looks to its protection not from an autonomous power state but rather as a "member of a future federation, voluntarily concluded, of the central and west European states," which would be a "United Nations of Europe."