IR Folks from Times Past

IR Folks from Times Past

Saturday, October 5, 2013

The Plunder of the Nations

Thomas Hobbes was a 17th century English philosopher whose most famous work is Leviathan, published in 1651 in the midst of the English civil war. This extract comes from the dedication to On the Citizen (De Cive), which first appeared in a privately printed Latin edition in 1642. It vividly expresses Hobbes’s point of departure in his philosophical quest and the revulsion he felt for the Roman conquest. His purpose, he suggests, is to discover a route to a secure peace among states, in which ambition and greed will be disarmed, and he sees the condition of endless war as arising from a failure in moral philosophy. (1187 words)

* * *

The Roman People had a saying . . . which came from the mouth of Marcus Cato, the Censor, and expressed the prejudice against Kings which they had conceived from their memory of the Tarquins and the principles of their commonwealth; the saying was that Kings should be classed as predatory animals. But what sort of animal was the Roman People? By the agency of citizens who took the names Africanus, Asiaticus, Macedonicus, Achaicus and so on from the nations they had robbed, that people plundered nearly all the world. So the words of Pontius Telesinus are no less wise than Cato's. As he reviewed the ranks of his army in the battle against Sulla at the Colline Gate, he cried that Rome itself must be demolished and destroyed, remarking that there would never be an end to Wolves preying upon the liberty of Italy, unless the forest in which they took refuge was cut down.

There are two maxims which are surely both true: Man is a God to man, and Man is a wolf to Man. The former is true of the relations of citizens with each other, the latter of relations between commonwealths. In justice and charity, the virtues of peace, citizens show some likeness to God. But between commonwealths, the wickedness of bad men compels the good too to have recourse, for their own protection, to the virtues of war, which are violence and fraud, i.e. to the predatory nature of beasts. Though men have a natural tendency to use rapacity as a term of abuse against each other, seeing their own actions reflected in others as in a mirror where left becomes right and right becomes left, natural right does not accept that anything that arises from the need for self-preservation is a vice. It may seem surprising that prejudice should so impose upon the mind of Cato, a man renowned for wisdom, and partiality should so overcome his reason, that he censured in Kings what he thought reasonable in his own people. But I have long been of the opinion that there was never an exceptional notion that found favour with the people nor a wisdom above the common level that could be appreciated by the average man; for either they do not understand it, or in understanding it, they bring it down to their own level. The famous deeds and sayings of the Greeks and Romans have been commended to History not by Reason but by their grandeur and often by that very wolf-like element which men deplore in each other; for the stream of History carries down through the centuries the memory of men's varied characters as well as of their public actions.

True Wisdom is simply the knowledge [scientia] of truth in every subject. Since it derives from the remembrance of things, which is prompted by their fixed and definite names, it is not a matter of momentary flashes of penetrating insight, but of right Reason, i.e. of Philosophy. For Philosophy opens the way from the observation of individual things to universal precepts. . . .

The Geometers have managed their province outstandingly. For whatever benefit comes to human life from observation of the stars, from mapping of lands, from reckoning of time and from long-distance navigation; whatever is beautiful in buildings, strong in defence-works and marvellous in machines, whatever in short distinguishes the modern world from the barbarity of the past, is almost wholly the gift of Geometry; for what we owe to Physics, Physics owes to Geometry. If the moral philosophers had done their job with equal success, I do not know what greater contribution human industry could have made to human happiness. For if the patterns of human action were known with the same certainty as the relations of magnitude in figures, ambition and greed, whose power rests on the false opinions of the common people about right and wrong [jus et iniuria], would be disarmed, and the human race would enjoy such secure peace that (apart from conflicts over space as the population grew) it seems unlikely that it would ever have to fight again.

But as things are, the war of the sword and the war of the pens is perpetual; there is no greater knowledge [scientia] of natural right and natural laws today than in the past; both parties to a dispute defend their right with the opinions of Philosophers; one and the same action is praised by some and criticized by others; a man now approves what at another time he condemns, and gives a different judgement of an action when he does it than when someone else does the very same thing. All these things are obvious signs that what moral Philosophers have written up to now has contributed nothing to the knowledge of truth; its appeal has not lain in enlightening the mind but in lending the influence of attractive and emotive language to hasty and superficial opinions. This part of Philosophy is in the same situation as the public roads, on which all men travel, and go to and fro, and some are enjoying a pleasant stroll and others are quarrelling, but they make no progress. The single reason for this situation seems to be that none of those who have dealt with this subject have employed a suitable starting point from which to teach it.

* * *

Hobbes and Machiavelli are usually considered the forerunners of Realism, but from this short extract we note a series of contrasts in their approach. Whereas Machiavelli glorified early republican Rome for perfecting the ways of military expansion, Hobbes made the people of Rome the villain of the piece. The very absurdity which Hobbes noted—Cato’s blindness in censuring the tyranny of kings but not the tyranny of republican imperialism—is also characteristic of Machiavelli, for whom the “liberty of Florence” seems necessarily to come at the expense of the liberty of others. Whereas Machiavelli foresaw humanity gripped by endless war, Hobbes in this remarkable passage forecasts the possibility of universal peace. Machiavelli and Hobbes are alike in insisting upon the right of states to self protection, but there are significant contrasts in their understanding of this right. It makes a great deal of difference whether glory (as with Machiavelli) or safety (as with Hobbes) is your watchword.

* * *
 
From Thomas Hobbes, On the Citizen, edited and translated by Richard Tuck and Michael Silverthorne (Cambridge University Press, 1998), 3-5. This is a new translation by Silverthorne that replaces the English translation of 1651, which the editors insist was unauthorized by Hobbes. The older translation, in a key passage, held that "were the nature of human actions as distinctly known as the nature of quantity in geometrical figures, the strength of avarice and ambition, which is sustained by the erroneous opinions of the vulgar as touching the nature of right and wrong, would presently faint and languish; and mankind should enjoy such an immortal peace, that unless it were for habitation, on supposition that the earth would grow too narrow for her inhabitants, there would hardly be left any pretence for war."
 
 
Portrait of Hobbes from Wikipedia.